
from spiritualnetworks.com
Heart disease is a leading threat to health, and people worry when they feel changes
in their heartbeat. Should clinicians trust descriptions of these palpitations? How should
clinicians and scientists model personal, phenomenological statements about what is
happening inside the body of a subject or patient? In an increasingly standardized,
scientific, and objective world of medicine, what role is there for a doctor’s intuitions and
instincts about a patient’s bodily sensations?
These are not simple questions, as they attempt to straddle a fundamental duality
between patients understood as embodied persons in an existential context of health and
disease, and humans understood as systems, as bio-machines modeled by science.
Clinicians collect measurements and interpret data about that category of object known as
a human body, and must compare this externalized, ostensibly objective, techno-scientific
knowledge to their patients’ description of what their bodies feel like. Like the Roman
god Janus, the healer faces two worlds. As modern medicine becomes more involved
with science, integrating these two domains requires ever-more flexibility,
thoughtfulness, and careful techniques for acquiring and modeling data. As complex as
these practical necessities are, science peers even deeper, into the meaning of the often
enigmatic gap that can exist between patient descriptions of the heart speeding up or
missing beats, and the lack of corresponding measurement of heart electrical output as
measured through electrocardiograms (ECG). Medicine needs good approaches for
distinguishing palpitations of psychosomatic origin from those with cardiac etiology, as
well as general guidelines for the trustworthiness of patient-reported data about their
bodily sensations. Science needs to understand what mechanisms in the brain, body, and
mind explain both accurate and inaccurate palpitations reports.
Knowledge of, and theories about, fluid dynamics, hematology, processing of cardiac
state by the peripheral nervous system, receptor activation, hormone binding, protein
signaling, up-regulation and down-regulation of genes, and models of perfusion support
sophisticated models of cardiodynamics. Yet the heart can be thought of in rather more
intuitive terms, as a pump made of muscle that moves oxygen-poor blood to the lungs,
and newly oxygenated blood to the rest of the body. Electrocardiograms show the
rhythms of this pumping as sometimes more regular and periodic and other times less so.
But how much personal knowledge do patients have about what the heart is doing?
Personal knowledge of the body is a problem for mechanistic science. While cardiac
periodicity is an object of scientific measurement, and therefore clinically and
epistemologically privileged for scientists constructing explanations, the personal
experience and phenomenological knowledge of the body may be considered merely
subjective opinion or anecdotal.
People introspecting about their interior sensations sometimes report to their doctor
that their heart is racing, pounding, or skipping beats. In some instances, such data are
compared to that from publically available sources such as ECG, and a diagnosis of
cardiac etiology is made, but in other cases doctors believe the patient is psychosomatically
cognizing benign heart rhythms as dangerous. When measurements of cardiodynamics do
not correspond well to unwelcome sensations of altered heartbeats, how should medicine
and science understand the discrepancy? This work addresses this problem directly,
by modeling the probabilities that a patient’s experience corresponds to
a medically important heart rhythm disorder. For the patient, feeling a change in
the rhythm or intensity of this fundamental aspect of ongoing embodied existence can
be very worrisome. When the cause is psychosomatic, medicine categorizes it as unexplained,
and cognitive neuroscience faces an explanatory challenge. Somewhere between the cardiac nerves,
brainstem, thalamus,and cortical regions, normal heart rhythms are processed as abnormal and
threatening, but why?
A true understanding of such a gap between personal bodily feelings and cardiac
measurement requires an implicit or explicit mapping of cardiographic, radiological, and
other data onto a description from the patient about what is going on inside their body, or
vice versa. This is not the sort of problem that cognitive science has heretofore usually
focused on, but the field of medical cognitive science can apply ideas from neuroscience
to come up with an explanation. Current evidence (Damasio, 2010) suggests a role for
multiple areas in the peripheral and central nervous systems that process cardiac rhythm
signals, which are cognized into feelings of skipping beats and other abnormal rhythms
(Barsky, 2000).
Such theoretical problems aside, clinicians must apply complex psychological,
anatomical, neurophysiological, and etiological concepts to interpret their patients’
symptom reports. What patients have to say about what is happening in their bodies must
be taken seriously, but not necessarily believed. Traditionally, a doctor might have had
some intuition about the reliability of a patient’s description of their heart fluttering or
racing and would consider the possibility that emotions, stress, and existential or
psychological issues partially or mostly explain the diagnosis. Yet the demands placed on
modern clinicians increasingly constrict the time they may spend listening to the patient,
making it harder for them to get a rich description of the proper existential context
framing the presenting complaint. As such, the need for quickly ascertaining the
probability that palpitation symptoms have a cardiac or psychosomatic etiology becomes
paramount.
What good is patient phenomenology in this new world of evidence-based medicine?
To determine this, I shall focus in particular on comparing the predictive utility of patient
palpitation reports for cardiac arrhythmias to other clinically predictive measures that do
not depend on introspective data from the patient. This predictivity will support the
differential diagnosis of cardiac-based palpitations against psychosomatic etiology, but
modeling how well symptoms correspond to physiological measurements can also serve
to operationalize what I will term “body cognition” and “body knowledge.” Palpitations
are usually defined as unwelcome awareness of cardiac activity (Barsky, 2000), such as
skipping, racing, or thumping heartbeats. Do people with such presenting complaints
have heart rhythm abnormalities requiring medical attention, benign heart rhythm
fluctuations, or normal heartbeats somehow sensed as strange, unpleasant, and abnormal?
Evidence suggests that patients reporting palpitations who have an anxiety disorder are
less likely to have arrhythmias (Abbott, 2005), but the reasons people with normal heart
rhythms report palpitations must be considered a mystery for science, and a challenge
(Barsky, 2000).